In the category $mathbf{Set}$ is “the product of an empty set of sets a one-element set”?
up vote
5
down vote
favorite
I was reading these notes on Category Theory and it said (paraphrased to add context):
Exercise 4: Explain why in $textbf{Set}$ (the Category of Sets), the product of an empty set of sets is a one-element set.
which I think is incorrect. The product of two empty sets (or any number) is empty because we are considering:
$$ emptyset times emptyset = { (a,b) : a in emptyset, b in emptyset } = emptyset$$
where $a in emptyset , b in emptyset$ are false, so the above is the $emptyset$ which is NOT a one element set (its a zero element set).
This should be trivial so I am assuming I am somewhere mis reading the natural language of the exercise. Someone help me catch where is it and what the answer should be? i.e. whats being asked and the answer?
category-theory direct-product
add a comment |
up vote
5
down vote
favorite
I was reading these notes on Category Theory and it said (paraphrased to add context):
Exercise 4: Explain why in $textbf{Set}$ (the Category of Sets), the product of an empty set of sets is a one-element set.
which I think is incorrect. The product of two empty sets (or any number) is empty because we are considering:
$$ emptyset times emptyset = { (a,b) : a in emptyset, b in emptyset } = emptyset$$
where $a in emptyset , b in emptyset$ are false, so the above is the $emptyset$ which is NOT a one element set (its a zero element set).
This should be trivial so I am assuming I am somewhere mis reading the natural language of the exercise. Someone help me catch where is it and what the answer should be? i.e. whats being asked and the answer?
category-theory direct-product
1
Your example is similar to asking why in arithmetic $0^0$ is taken to be $1$ rather than $0$
– Henry
Nov 21 at 8:22
2
Related : math.stackexchange.com/questions/1991522/…
– Arnaud D.
Nov 21 at 13:20
add a comment |
up vote
5
down vote
favorite
up vote
5
down vote
favorite
I was reading these notes on Category Theory and it said (paraphrased to add context):
Exercise 4: Explain why in $textbf{Set}$ (the Category of Sets), the product of an empty set of sets is a one-element set.
which I think is incorrect. The product of two empty sets (or any number) is empty because we are considering:
$$ emptyset times emptyset = { (a,b) : a in emptyset, b in emptyset } = emptyset$$
where $a in emptyset , b in emptyset$ are false, so the above is the $emptyset$ which is NOT a one element set (its a zero element set).
This should be trivial so I am assuming I am somewhere mis reading the natural language of the exercise. Someone help me catch where is it and what the answer should be? i.e. whats being asked and the answer?
category-theory direct-product
I was reading these notes on Category Theory and it said (paraphrased to add context):
Exercise 4: Explain why in $textbf{Set}$ (the Category of Sets), the product of an empty set of sets is a one-element set.
which I think is incorrect. The product of two empty sets (or any number) is empty because we are considering:
$$ emptyset times emptyset = { (a,b) : a in emptyset, b in emptyset } = emptyset$$
where $a in emptyset , b in emptyset$ are false, so the above is the $emptyset$ which is NOT a one element set (its a zero element set).
This should be trivial so I am assuming I am somewhere mis reading the natural language of the exercise. Someone help me catch where is it and what the answer should be? i.e. whats being asked and the answer?
category-theory direct-product
category-theory direct-product
edited Nov 21 at 14:11
Asaf Karagila♦
300k32421751
300k32421751
asked Nov 21 at 2:12
Pinocchio
1,85121753
1,85121753
1
Your example is similar to asking why in arithmetic $0^0$ is taken to be $1$ rather than $0$
– Henry
Nov 21 at 8:22
2
Related : math.stackexchange.com/questions/1991522/…
– Arnaud D.
Nov 21 at 13:20
add a comment |
1
Your example is similar to asking why in arithmetic $0^0$ is taken to be $1$ rather than $0$
– Henry
Nov 21 at 8:22
2
Related : math.stackexchange.com/questions/1991522/…
– Arnaud D.
Nov 21 at 13:20
1
1
Your example is similar to asking why in arithmetic $0^0$ is taken to be $1$ rather than $0$
– Henry
Nov 21 at 8:22
Your example is similar to asking why in arithmetic $0^0$ is taken to be $1$ rather than $0$
– Henry
Nov 21 at 8:22
2
2
Related : math.stackexchange.com/questions/1991522/…
– Arnaud D.
Nov 21 at 13:20
Related : math.stackexchange.com/questions/1991522/…
– Arnaud D.
Nov 21 at 13:20
add a comment |
4 Answers
4
active
oldest
votes
up vote
7
down vote
accepted
What the exercise is saying is the following: let $mathcal{C}$ be an empty family of sets (awkward, but $mathcal{C}$ is just isomorphic to $emptyset$). Then, $prod,mathcal{C}=prodlimits_{Cinmathcal{C}},C$ has one element. Simply put, $$prod,emptyset=prod_{Cinemptyset},C$$ has exactly one element. This is the same situation that gives rise to $a^0=1$. The real question is where on heaven this element comes from, and what exactly it is.
You can interpret $prod,emptyset$ as the set of all functions from $emptyset$ to itself. The only function there is the empty function $emptyset$. Therefore, $prod,emptyset={emptyset}$.
3
So it's not like a product of empty sets, but rather an empty product of sets, right? And thus its having one element is analogous to how a numerical empty product equals 1, and not 0.
– The_Sympathizer
Nov 21 at 6:55
Yep, that's the idea.
– Batominovski
Nov 21 at 7:45
add a comment |
up vote
5
down vote
A product $Pi_{iin I} A_i$ of objects in a category is an object $B$ and a collection of morphisms $pi_i: Bto A_i$ such that for any object $C$ and collection of morphisms $d_i:Cto A_i,$ there is a unique morphism $f:Cto B$ such that $d_i=pi_icirc f.$ Note such a $(B,pi_i)$ may not exist and is generally not unique, although if $(B,pi_i)$ and $(B',pi_i')$ both satisfy the condition, there is a canonical isomorphism between $B$ and $B'$. If $I$ is empty, then there are no $pi_i$ and the definition reduces to an object $B$ such that for any $C$ there is a unique $f:Cto B$ (i.e. $B$ is a terminal object).
Specifying to the category Set, the sets that have a unique map into them from any set are exactly the singletons (if the set had more than one element there would be multiple maps into it from any nonempty set; if it had zero elements, there would be none). So any singleton is a nullary product, and as promised, any two singletons have a canonical bijection between them. In a set theoretical sense, one may define the nullary cartesian product to be ${phi}$ for the sake of having a well-defined operation (just as one defines the binary cartesian product as the set of ordered pairs), but from a category theory perspective these are best thought of as nice representatives of a whole collection of product objects, which are all isomorphic to one another.
add a comment |
up vote
4
down vote
If the interpretation is $X^0$ then the answer is obvious.
It's just the question of what the set $X^0$ is which is the set of functions mapping nothing (the empty set) to a set $X$ which obviously is only the function that does "nothing" (the single element in the set "1"). Formally $X^0 = { f: emptyset to X } $ (the set of functions from the empty set to $X$) now what we want to figure out is what "this set really is". First we recall that a function is simply a relation defined by the graph of $f$ i.e. $f subseteq A times B$ such that $f := { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in A, exists b in B }$. In this case we have $A = emptyset$ so all this actually become the following:
$$X^0 = { f: emptyset to X } = { f subseteq A times B mid f: emptyset to X } $$
which is equal to:
$$ { f subseteq A times B mid f: emptyset to X } = { { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in emptyset , exists b in B } } = { emptyset } $$
so,
$$ X^0 = { emptyset }$$
the key is realizing that $f = { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in emptyset , exists b in B } = emptyset$ because if we try to form a set of pairs where the first element of the pair comes from the empty set, then of course we won't form any pair becuase $a in emptyset$ is false.
To make it really clear, recall the graph (i.e. relation set) of a function $f$ is the set of pairs $ f = { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in A, exists b in B } $ which is why we get as a final answer the empty set inside a set (since a function is really just a relation saying how we pair up the first element to the second element and $f$ induces this pairing/relation). In the end $X^0$ is just the set of all function from the empty set to $B$ but a function is a set of "pairs". This set of pairs ends up being empty because we can never select elements for its first location since we are trying to select things form the empty set.
This is a nice answer; could be better if it were less ambiguous in its notation, therefore slightly clearer. E.g., the second equality is rather unreasonable except to those with sufficient familiarity with set theory to extrapolate the missing pieces. Nonetheless, +1.
– Musa Al-hassy
Nov 22 at 10:36
@MusaAl-hassy ok I added more details, it should be more accessible to everyone now, right? Thanks for the feedback! :)
– Pinocchio
Nov 22 at 18:08
add a comment |
up vote
3
down vote
Since no-one has said this explicitly:
Yes, you are misreading the language of the question. The question is asking for
$$prodlimits_{x in emptyset} x$$
It's the difference between "the product of an empty set of sets" and "the product of a set of empty sets".
add a comment |
4 Answers
4
active
oldest
votes
4 Answers
4
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
up vote
7
down vote
accepted
What the exercise is saying is the following: let $mathcal{C}$ be an empty family of sets (awkward, but $mathcal{C}$ is just isomorphic to $emptyset$). Then, $prod,mathcal{C}=prodlimits_{Cinmathcal{C}},C$ has one element. Simply put, $$prod,emptyset=prod_{Cinemptyset},C$$ has exactly one element. This is the same situation that gives rise to $a^0=1$. The real question is where on heaven this element comes from, and what exactly it is.
You can interpret $prod,emptyset$ as the set of all functions from $emptyset$ to itself. The only function there is the empty function $emptyset$. Therefore, $prod,emptyset={emptyset}$.
3
So it's not like a product of empty sets, but rather an empty product of sets, right? And thus its having one element is analogous to how a numerical empty product equals 1, and not 0.
– The_Sympathizer
Nov 21 at 6:55
Yep, that's the idea.
– Batominovski
Nov 21 at 7:45
add a comment |
up vote
7
down vote
accepted
What the exercise is saying is the following: let $mathcal{C}$ be an empty family of sets (awkward, but $mathcal{C}$ is just isomorphic to $emptyset$). Then, $prod,mathcal{C}=prodlimits_{Cinmathcal{C}},C$ has one element. Simply put, $$prod,emptyset=prod_{Cinemptyset},C$$ has exactly one element. This is the same situation that gives rise to $a^0=1$. The real question is where on heaven this element comes from, and what exactly it is.
You can interpret $prod,emptyset$ as the set of all functions from $emptyset$ to itself. The only function there is the empty function $emptyset$. Therefore, $prod,emptyset={emptyset}$.
3
So it's not like a product of empty sets, but rather an empty product of sets, right? And thus its having one element is analogous to how a numerical empty product equals 1, and not 0.
– The_Sympathizer
Nov 21 at 6:55
Yep, that's the idea.
– Batominovski
Nov 21 at 7:45
add a comment |
up vote
7
down vote
accepted
up vote
7
down vote
accepted
What the exercise is saying is the following: let $mathcal{C}$ be an empty family of sets (awkward, but $mathcal{C}$ is just isomorphic to $emptyset$). Then, $prod,mathcal{C}=prodlimits_{Cinmathcal{C}},C$ has one element. Simply put, $$prod,emptyset=prod_{Cinemptyset},C$$ has exactly one element. This is the same situation that gives rise to $a^0=1$. The real question is where on heaven this element comes from, and what exactly it is.
You can interpret $prod,emptyset$ as the set of all functions from $emptyset$ to itself. The only function there is the empty function $emptyset$. Therefore, $prod,emptyset={emptyset}$.
What the exercise is saying is the following: let $mathcal{C}$ be an empty family of sets (awkward, but $mathcal{C}$ is just isomorphic to $emptyset$). Then, $prod,mathcal{C}=prodlimits_{Cinmathcal{C}},C$ has one element. Simply put, $$prod,emptyset=prod_{Cinemptyset},C$$ has exactly one element. This is the same situation that gives rise to $a^0=1$. The real question is where on heaven this element comes from, and what exactly it is.
You can interpret $prod,emptyset$ as the set of all functions from $emptyset$ to itself. The only function there is the empty function $emptyset$. Therefore, $prod,emptyset={emptyset}$.
answered Nov 21 at 2:27
Batominovski
31.8k23190
31.8k23190
3
So it's not like a product of empty sets, but rather an empty product of sets, right? And thus its having one element is analogous to how a numerical empty product equals 1, and not 0.
– The_Sympathizer
Nov 21 at 6:55
Yep, that's the idea.
– Batominovski
Nov 21 at 7:45
add a comment |
3
So it's not like a product of empty sets, but rather an empty product of sets, right? And thus its having one element is analogous to how a numerical empty product equals 1, and not 0.
– The_Sympathizer
Nov 21 at 6:55
Yep, that's the idea.
– Batominovski
Nov 21 at 7:45
3
3
So it's not like a product of empty sets, but rather an empty product of sets, right? And thus its having one element is analogous to how a numerical empty product equals 1, and not 0.
– The_Sympathizer
Nov 21 at 6:55
So it's not like a product of empty sets, but rather an empty product of sets, right? And thus its having one element is analogous to how a numerical empty product equals 1, and not 0.
– The_Sympathizer
Nov 21 at 6:55
Yep, that's the idea.
– Batominovski
Nov 21 at 7:45
Yep, that's the idea.
– Batominovski
Nov 21 at 7:45
add a comment |
up vote
5
down vote
A product $Pi_{iin I} A_i$ of objects in a category is an object $B$ and a collection of morphisms $pi_i: Bto A_i$ such that for any object $C$ and collection of morphisms $d_i:Cto A_i,$ there is a unique morphism $f:Cto B$ such that $d_i=pi_icirc f.$ Note such a $(B,pi_i)$ may not exist and is generally not unique, although if $(B,pi_i)$ and $(B',pi_i')$ both satisfy the condition, there is a canonical isomorphism between $B$ and $B'$. If $I$ is empty, then there are no $pi_i$ and the definition reduces to an object $B$ such that for any $C$ there is a unique $f:Cto B$ (i.e. $B$ is a terminal object).
Specifying to the category Set, the sets that have a unique map into them from any set are exactly the singletons (if the set had more than one element there would be multiple maps into it from any nonempty set; if it had zero elements, there would be none). So any singleton is a nullary product, and as promised, any two singletons have a canonical bijection between them. In a set theoretical sense, one may define the nullary cartesian product to be ${phi}$ for the sake of having a well-defined operation (just as one defines the binary cartesian product as the set of ordered pairs), but from a category theory perspective these are best thought of as nice representatives of a whole collection of product objects, which are all isomorphic to one another.
add a comment |
up vote
5
down vote
A product $Pi_{iin I} A_i$ of objects in a category is an object $B$ and a collection of morphisms $pi_i: Bto A_i$ such that for any object $C$ and collection of morphisms $d_i:Cto A_i,$ there is a unique morphism $f:Cto B$ such that $d_i=pi_icirc f.$ Note such a $(B,pi_i)$ may not exist and is generally not unique, although if $(B,pi_i)$ and $(B',pi_i')$ both satisfy the condition, there is a canonical isomorphism between $B$ and $B'$. If $I$ is empty, then there are no $pi_i$ and the definition reduces to an object $B$ such that for any $C$ there is a unique $f:Cto B$ (i.e. $B$ is a terminal object).
Specifying to the category Set, the sets that have a unique map into them from any set are exactly the singletons (if the set had more than one element there would be multiple maps into it from any nonempty set; if it had zero elements, there would be none). So any singleton is a nullary product, and as promised, any two singletons have a canonical bijection between them. In a set theoretical sense, one may define the nullary cartesian product to be ${phi}$ for the sake of having a well-defined operation (just as one defines the binary cartesian product as the set of ordered pairs), but from a category theory perspective these are best thought of as nice representatives of a whole collection of product objects, which are all isomorphic to one another.
add a comment |
up vote
5
down vote
up vote
5
down vote
A product $Pi_{iin I} A_i$ of objects in a category is an object $B$ and a collection of morphisms $pi_i: Bto A_i$ such that for any object $C$ and collection of morphisms $d_i:Cto A_i,$ there is a unique morphism $f:Cto B$ such that $d_i=pi_icirc f.$ Note such a $(B,pi_i)$ may not exist and is generally not unique, although if $(B,pi_i)$ and $(B',pi_i')$ both satisfy the condition, there is a canonical isomorphism between $B$ and $B'$. If $I$ is empty, then there are no $pi_i$ and the definition reduces to an object $B$ such that for any $C$ there is a unique $f:Cto B$ (i.e. $B$ is a terminal object).
Specifying to the category Set, the sets that have a unique map into them from any set are exactly the singletons (if the set had more than one element there would be multiple maps into it from any nonempty set; if it had zero elements, there would be none). So any singleton is a nullary product, and as promised, any two singletons have a canonical bijection between them. In a set theoretical sense, one may define the nullary cartesian product to be ${phi}$ for the sake of having a well-defined operation (just as one defines the binary cartesian product as the set of ordered pairs), but from a category theory perspective these are best thought of as nice representatives of a whole collection of product objects, which are all isomorphic to one another.
A product $Pi_{iin I} A_i$ of objects in a category is an object $B$ and a collection of morphisms $pi_i: Bto A_i$ such that for any object $C$ and collection of morphisms $d_i:Cto A_i,$ there is a unique morphism $f:Cto B$ such that $d_i=pi_icirc f.$ Note such a $(B,pi_i)$ may not exist and is generally not unique, although if $(B,pi_i)$ and $(B',pi_i')$ both satisfy the condition, there is a canonical isomorphism between $B$ and $B'$. If $I$ is empty, then there are no $pi_i$ and the definition reduces to an object $B$ such that for any $C$ there is a unique $f:Cto B$ (i.e. $B$ is a terminal object).
Specifying to the category Set, the sets that have a unique map into them from any set are exactly the singletons (if the set had more than one element there would be multiple maps into it from any nonempty set; if it had zero elements, there would be none). So any singleton is a nullary product, and as promised, any two singletons have a canonical bijection between them. In a set theoretical sense, one may define the nullary cartesian product to be ${phi}$ for the sake of having a well-defined operation (just as one defines the binary cartesian product as the set of ordered pairs), but from a category theory perspective these are best thought of as nice representatives of a whole collection of product objects, which are all isomorphic to one another.
edited Nov 21 at 5:18
answered Nov 21 at 5:13
spaceisdarkgreen
31.7k21552
31.7k21552
add a comment |
add a comment |
up vote
4
down vote
If the interpretation is $X^0$ then the answer is obvious.
It's just the question of what the set $X^0$ is which is the set of functions mapping nothing (the empty set) to a set $X$ which obviously is only the function that does "nothing" (the single element in the set "1"). Formally $X^0 = { f: emptyset to X } $ (the set of functions from the empty set to $X$) now what we want to figure out is what "this set really is". First we recall that a function is simply a relation defined by the graph of $f$ i.e. $f subseteq A times B$ such that $f := { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in A, exists b in B }$. In this case we have $A = emptyset$ so all this actually become the following:
$$X^0 = { f: emptyset to X } = { f subseteq A times B mid f: emptyset to X } $$
which is equal to:
$$ { f subseteq A times B mid f: emptyset to X } = { { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in emptyset , exists b in B } } = { emptyset } $$
so,
$$ X^0 = { emptyset }$$
the key is realizing that $f = { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in emptyset , exists b in B } = emptyset$ because if we try to form a set of pairs where the first element of the pair comes from the empty set, then of course we won't form any pair becuase $a in emptyset$ is false.
To make it really clear, recall the graph (i.e. relation set) of a function $f$ is the set of pairs $ f = { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in A, exists b in B } $ which is why we get as a final answer the empty set inside a set (since a function is really just a relation saying how we pair up the first element to the second element and $f$ induces this pairing/relation). In the end $X^0$ is just the set of all function from the empty set to $B$ but a function is a set of "pairs". This set of pairs ends up being empty because we can never select elements for its first location since we are trying to select things form the empty set.
This is a nice answer; could be better if it were less ambiguous in its notation, therefore slightly clearer. E.g., the second equality is rather unreasonable except to those with sufficient familiarity with set theory to extrapolate the missing pieces. Nonetheless, +1.
– Musa Al-hassy
Nov 22 at 10:36
@MusaAl-hassy ok I added more details, it should be more accessible to everyone now, right? Thanks for the feedback! :)
– Pinocchio
Nov 22 at 18:08
add a comment |
up vote
4
down vote
If the interpretation is $X^0$ then the answer is obvious.
It's just the question of what the set $X^0$ is which is the set of functions mapping nothing (the empty set) to a set $X$ which obviously is only the function that does "nothing" (the single element in the set "1"). Formally $X^0 = { f: emptyset to X } $ (the set of functions from the empty set to $X$) now what we want to figure out is what "this set really is". First we recall that a function is simply a relation defined by the graph of $f$ i.e. $f subseteq A times B$ such that $f := { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in A, exists b in B }$. In this case we have $A = emptyset$ so all this actually become the following:
$$X^0 = { f: emptyset to X } = { f subseteq A times B mid f: emptyset to X } $$
which is equal to:
$$ { f subseteq A times B mid f: emptyset to X } = { { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in emptyset , exists b in B } } = { emptyset } $$
so,
$$ X^0 = { emptyset }$$
the key is realizing that $f = { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in emptyset , exists b in B } = emptyset$ because if we try to form a set of pairs where the first element of the pair comes from the empty set, then of course we won't form any pair becuase $a in emptyset$ is false.
To make it really clear, recall the graph (i.e. relation set) of a function $f$ is the set of pairs $ f = { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in A, exists b in B } $ which is why we get as a final answer the empty set inside a set (since a function is really just a relation saying how we pair up the first element to the second element and $f$ induces this pairing/relation). In the end $X^0$ is just the set of all function from the empty set to $B$ but a function is a set of "pairs". This set of pairs ends up being empty because we can never select elements for its first location since we are trying to select things form the empty set.
This is a nice answer; could be better if it were less ambiguous in its notation, therefore slightly clearer. E.g., the second equality is rather unreasonable except to those with sufficient familiarity with set theory to extrapolate the missing pieces. Nonetheless, +1.
– Musa Al-hassy
Nov 22 at 10:36
@MusaAl-hassy ok I added more details, it should be more accessible to everyone now, right? Thanks for the feedback! :)
– Pinocchio
Nov 22 at 18:08
add a comment |
up vote
4
down vote
up vote
4
down vote
If the interpretation is $X^0$ then the answer is obvious.
It's just the question of what the set $X^0$ is which is the set of functions mapping nothing (the empty set) to a set $X$ which obviously is only the function that does "nothing" (the single element in the set "1"). Formally $X^0 = { f: emptyset to X } $ (the set of functions from the empty set to $X$) now what we want to figure out is what "this set really is". First we recall that a function is simply a relation defined by the graph of $f$ i.e. $f subseteq A times B$ such that $f := { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in A, exists b in B }$. In this case we have $A = emptyset$ so all this actually become the following:
$$X^0 = { f: emptyset to X } = { f subseteq A times B mid f: emptyset to X } $$
which is equal to:
$$ { f subseteq A times B mid f: emptyset to X } = { { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in emptyset , exists b in B } } = { emptyset } $$
so,
$$ X^0 = { emptyset }$$
the key is realizing that $f = { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in emptyset , exists b in B } = emptyset$ because if we try to form a set of pairs where the first element of the pair comes from the empty set, then of course we won't form any pair becuase $a in emptyset$ is false.
To make it really clear, recall the graph (i.e. relation set) of a function $f$ is the set of pairs $ f = { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in A, exists b in B } $ which is why we get as a final answer the empty set inside a set (since a function is really just a relation saying how we pair up the first element to the second element and $f$ induces this pairing/relation). In the end $X^0$ is just the set of all function from the empty set to $B$ but a function is a set of "pairs". This set of pairs ends up being empty because we can never select elements for its first location since we are trying to select things form the empty set.
If the interpretation is $X^0$ then the answer is obvious.
It's just the question of what the set $X^0$ is which is the set of functions mapping nothing (the empty set) to a set $X$ which obviously is only the function that does "nothing" (the single element in the set "1"). Formally $X^0 = { f: emptyset to X } $ (the set of functions from the empty set to $X$) now what we want to figure out is what "this set really is". First we recall that a function is simply a relation defined by the graph of $f$ i.e. $f subseteq A times B$ such that $f := { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in A, exists b in B }$. In this case we have $A = emptyset$ so all this actually become the following:
$$X^0 = { f: emptyset to X } = { f subseteq A times B mid f: emptyset to X } $$
which is equal to:
$$ { f subseteq A times B mid f: emptyset to X } = { { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in emptyset , exists b in B } } = { emptyset } $$
so,
$$ X^0 = { emptyset }$$
the key is realizing that $f = { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in emptyset , exists b in B } = emptyset$ because if we try to form a set of pairs where the first element of the pair comes from the empty set, then of course we won't form any pair becuase $a in emptyset$ is false.
To make it really clear, recall the graph (i.e. relation set) of a function $f$ is the set of pairs $ f = { (a,b) in A times B : forall a in A, exists b in B } $ which is why we get as a final answer the empty set inside a set (since a function is really just a relation saying how we pair up the first element to the second element and $f$ induces this pairing/relation). In the end $X^0$ is just the set of all function from the empty set to $B$ but a function is a set of "pairs". This set of pairs ends up being empty because we can never select elements for its first location since we are trying to select things form the empty set.
edited Nov 22 at 18:14
answered Nov 21 at 2:38
Pinocchio
1,85121753
1,85121753
This is a nice answer; could be better if it were less ambiguous in its notation, therefore slightly clearer. E.g., the second equality is rather unreasonable except to those with sufficient familiarity with set theory to extrapolate the missing pieces. Nonetheless, +1.
– Musa Al-hassy
Nov 22 at 10:36
@MusaAl-hassy ok I added more details, it should be more accessible to everyone now, right? Thanks for the feedback! :)
– Pinocchio
Nov 22 at 18:08
add a comment |
This is a nice answer; could be better if it were less ambiguous in its notation, therefore slightly clearer. E.g., the second equality is rather unreasonable except to those with sufficient familiarity with set theory to extrapolate the missing pieces. Nonetheless, +1.
– Musa Al-hassy
Nov 22 at 10:36
@MusaAl-hassy ok I added more details, it should be more accessible to everyone now, right? Thanks for the feedback! :)
– Pinocchio
Nov 22 at 18:08
This is a nice answer; could be better if it were less ambiguous in its notation, therefore slightly clearer. E.g., the second equality is rather unreasonable except to those with sufficient familiarity with set theory to extrapolate the missing pieces. Nonetheless, +1.
– Musa Al-hassy
Nov 22 at 10:36
This is a nice answer; could be better if it were less ambiguous in its notation, therefore slightly clearer. E.g., the second equality is rather unreasonable except to those with sufficient familiarity with set theory to extrapolate the missing pieces. Nonetheless, +1.
– Musa Al-hassy
Nov 22 at 10:36
@MusaAl-hassy ok I added more details, it should be more accessible to everyone now, right? Thanks for the feedback! :)
– Pinocchio
Nov 22 at 18:08
@MusaAl-hassy ok I added more details, it should be more accessible to everyone now, right? Thanks for the feedback! :)
– Pinocchio
Nov 22 at 18:08
add a comment |
up vote
3
down vote
Since no-one has said this explicitly:
Yes, you are misreading the language of the question. The question is asking for
$$prodlimits_{x in emptyset} x$$
It's the difference between "the product of an empty set of sets" and "the product of a set of empty sets".
add a comment |
up vote
3
down vote
Since no-one has said this explicitly:
Yes, you are misreading the language of the question. The question is asking for
$$prodlimits_{x in emptyset} x$$
It's the difference between "the product of an empty set of sets" and "the product of a set of empty sets".
add a comment |
up vote
3
down vote
up vote
3
down vote
Since no-one has said this explicitly:
Yes, you are misreading the language of the question. The question is asking for
$$prodlimits_{x in emptyset} x$$
It's the difference between "the product of an empty set of sets" and "the product of a set of empty sets".
Since no-one has said this explicitly:
Yes, you are misreading the language of the question. The question is asking for
$$prodlimits_{x in emptyset} x$$
It's the difference between "the product of an empty set of sets" and "the product of a set of empty sets".
answered Nov 21 at 9:52
Christopher
6,30311628
6,30311628
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.
Please pay close attention to the following guidance:
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3007160%2fin-the-category-mathbfset-is-the-product-of-an-empty-set-of-sets-a-one-ele%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
1
Your example is similar to asking why in arithmetic $0^0$ is taken to be $1$ rather than $0$
– Henry
Nov 21 at 8:22
2
Related : math.stackexchange.com/questions/1991522/…
– Arnaud D.
Nov 21 at 13:20